Which Action Best Illustrates The Concept Of Religious Radicalism

Abstract

In the past decades the world has witnessed a remarkable resurgence of what might be called religious extremism or radicalism. In the United States, the Bush administration violated the principle of the separation of church and state, and signs of violent religiosity could also be discerned in the physical attacks on physicians performing abortions.

An even more radical form of religious extremism can be found in the Islamic world in the resurgence of Islamist movements, some of them preaching hatred against the West and advocating violent activism. Especially since September 11, 2001 (Twin Towers), March 11, 2004 (Madrid), July 5, 2005 (London), November 2, 2004 (the murder of Theo van Gogh in Amsterdam), and the Danish Cartoon Crisis (2006) there is an increasing attention to the religious roots of terrorism1 and radical Islamism in particular.2

The focus of this article is an analysis of the classical models of the relation between state and religion against the backdrop of the new religious radicalism. Does religious terrorism and radicalism necessitate us to rethink the relation between state and religion? My answer is that it does.

We can discern five models of thinking about the relationship between state and religion.3 These models are: 1) political atheism, 2) the religiously neutral state, 3) multiculturalism, 4) state church, and 5) theocracy.

In this article I want to analyze the different models and gauge which would be most appropriate to respond to the new challenges we are facing. My conclusion is that the idea of the religiously neutral state (model 2) is better adapted to the present challenges than the other models available. Political atheism (model 1) and theocracy (model 5) are both incompatible with liberal democracy. The idea of a state church (model 4) is no longer a viable alternative in a society that is deeply religiously divided. What is left are the religiously neutral state (model 2) and the multicultural state (model 3). The conclusion of my analysis is that the religiously neutral state is best adapted to incorporate religious and ethnic minorities in European liberal democracies.

This analysis is made against the backdrop of the revitalization of the ideology of model 5: theocracy. Religious terrorists are inspired by a worldview that is antithetical towards the basis of a liberal democratic society. For that reason this article can also be read as an attempt to formulate an answer to the “spiritual challenge” presented by religious extremism and religious terrorism.

1. Five models for the relation of state and religion

The first model is what we could call “political atheism.” It could also be labeled “totalitarian atheism.” In this model atheism is a state doctrine. Atheism is not regarded as a private conviction that God does not exist or that the reasons for believing in God’s existence are inconclusive, and so we better suspend our judgment, but as an official state policy aiming to eradicate all sympathy for religious ideas, and the idea that God exists in particular. Adherents of political atheism make a plea for an atheist state that would foster atheist convictions in its citizenry. This would require a tremendous power of the state, of course, and therefore the connection with totalitarianism is evident.4 The state would have to control the minds of its citizens into the smallest details, exactly like what happened in Orwell’s Ninety Eighty Four or in the German Democratic Republic. Political atheism is just as totalitarian, one might say, as the ambitions of the Catholic church at the time of the Inquisition (abolished as late as 1820) or—to a lesser degree—in the period when the church tried to suppress freedom of thought with an index of prohibited books (1559-1966).5

Although the atheist state existed for a considerable time (“considerable” especially for those who suffered under its regime), it was not as long as the period of Catholic suppression of free thought. The atheist state was inaugurated in 1917 with the Russian Revolution, and ended with the fall of the Berlin Wall in 1989 and the subsequent demise of the Soviet Empire. This means that political atheism reigned throughout the greater part of the twentieth century, in particular if we agree with the French journalist Jean Daniel (1920-) who said that the twentieth century started with the First World War and ended with the fall of the Berlin Wall.6

The attitude of the state regarding religion was strongly influenced by the writings of Karl Marx (1818-83). Religion, according to Marx, was false consciousness. Criticism of religion was an essential part of social criticism, wrote Marx in his notorious introduction to Zur Kritik der Hegelschen Rechtsphilosophie (1843-4).7 Man creates his religion, religion does not create man.8

So far, non-Marxists could also subscribe to this criticism of religion. The necessity of religious criticism was not something that Marx was the first to proclaim, but an integral part of the work of the Young Hegelians, Ludwig Feuerbach (1804-72) being the most prominent among them. In Das Wesen des Christentums (1841) Feuerbach contended that God was a creation of human imagination.9 What distinguishes Marxist criticism of religion from the criticism of Feuerbach, is that the criticism of Marx was the basis of Stalin’s and Lenin’s work that made this critique an essential part of state activity. It is the state that has to free people from the pernicious illusions created by religion. The state has to liberate people from religion for the same reasons that a modern state looks after the health of its citizens.10

In this respect, this approach differs to a great extent from contemporary Western authors who represent atheist positions in public debate.11 Contemporary atheism, as advocated by such authors as Richard Dawkins,12 Sam Harris,13 Christopher Hitchens,14 Daniel Dennett,15 and others (brought together under the banner of “the New Atheism”),16 is not meant as a state policy. For the authors mentioned, atheism is a private conviction. This “private atheism” respects the right of every citizen to choose a religion but also to reject a religion or even all religions.

The second model is the religiously neutral state. The most well known brand of this model is the French laïcité. The French republic is even organized around the principle of laïcité according to a French commission (known as the commission Stasi, named after its chairman Bernard Stasi) set up by president Chirac in order to reformulate the ideals of the Republic.17 All democratic states respect liberty of conscience and the principle of nondiscrimination. But only the French republic is based on laïcité as a fundamental principle.18Laïcité is based on three indissoluble values: freedom of conscience (liberté de conscience), equality before the law (égalité en droit), and the neutrality of political power (neutralité du pouvoir politique).19Laïcité is far from curtailing freedom of religion. On the contrary, it is the central presupposition under which freedom of religion can flourish. Laïcité makes it possible for every individual citizen to decide for himself what choices to make with regard to his spiritual and religious life (sa vie spirituelle ou religieuse).20 The equality before the law prohibits all discrimination or force and the state does not give privileges to any of the spiritual creeds.

Laïcité has roots in European history, going back to ancient Greece, the Renaissance, and the Reformation.21 It is intimately connected with the Edict of Nantes (1598) issued by Henry IV of France to give the French Calvinists (Huguenots) substantial rights in a country that was predominantly Catholic.22

The movement of laïcité aimed at realizing what could be characterized as “political secularism”: the aim of separating the state from religious confession. It is more often characterized as secularism tout court.23 It is the explicit aim of political secularism not to advocate for or against religion. The state must remain “neutral.” All religions (as far as they do not advocate violence) may be represented in society, but none of them has a privileged position. Upholding religion is not a task of the state.24

In a system operating under the banner of laïcité the state is not allowed to make favorable propaganda for religion. There is also a ban on financing churches and other religious institutions. This element of political secularism is usually characterized as “the separation of church and state.”25

The pretence of political secularism is that with this approach the state does not manifest an antireligious outlook as its critics all too often contend. The commission Stasi distinguishes between two models of laïcité. The first is combative and anticlerical. It was defended by Émile Combes (1835-1921). The second model is more concerned with the separation of church and state and regards all spiritual options with equal respect. This second approach, more liberal and tolerant, goes back to Jules Ferry (1832-93), Jean Jaurès (1859-1914), and Aristide Briand (1862-1932).26

There are several varieties of the religiously neutral state: the French model (laïcité), the American “Wall of Separation,”27 the Turkish model, and others. Those empirical manifestations of the religiously neutral state show considerable differences, and we should not identify the ideal of the religiously neutral state uncritically with one of its empirical manifestations (“You are in favour of the religiously neutral state? Oh, than you must be in favour of a ban of headscarves on public schools”).28

The third model is the “multicultural” or “multidenominational state.”29 This model intends to treat all religions equally by helping them equally. In other words, the state does not favor Christianity over Buddhism, or vice versa, but it treats Christianity on an equal basis with Buddhism. If Christianity gets state subsidies for its preachers, the maintenance of its churches, or the organization of its chaplains, Buddhism can claim subsidies as well. If Christian institutions are state-funded, other religious denominations can claim funding. Adherents of the multicultural state see this as “equal treatment.”

The question is, of course, whether this approach is correct. Supporting all the religious life and worldviews equally can still imply unequal treatment of nonreligious attitudes towards life. Placing all religions on equal footing can still imply discrimination of nonreligious views, contend the critics of multiculturalism.30 We will discuss this argument later.

The third model is sometimes characterized as “pluralism” or the “pluralist state.” But that is somewhat misleading because political secularism (the second model) aims to serve pluralism, too. The choice seems to be between “spontaneous pluralism” or “not state-supported pluralism” (second model) on the one hand and “state-organized pluralism” (third model) on the other hand.

The fourth model is the established church. According to this model state and church have an intimate connection in upholding the public order. That does not imply that religions other than the official one are suppressed, but they do not have priority. This discrimination is usually justified on a historical basis. The religion that was first adopted in the territory of the state gets more attention and enjoys special privileges, as is the case with the Anglican church in the United Kingdom.

The fifth model is theocracy. This is the exact opposite of political atheism. There is one religion that is favored above other religions, and other religions are suppressed—often by law and force. This model radicalizes the tendency inherent in the model of the state church. Examples are Saudi Arabia and Iran.

Presented in the order I have described above, the five models show an increasing influence of religion on the sphere of the state. Political atheism (model 1) excludes all influence by all the means available. Political secularism (model 2) tries to neutralize the state. Multiculturalism (model 3) interprets “neutrality” as giving aid to religion in general. The idea of the state church (model 4) opts for one specific religion on historical grounds. And theocracy (model 5) prescribes one religion and tries to suppress all other religions by force.

It requires no elaborate argument that the first (political atheism) and the fifth model (theocracy) are irreconcilable with the central tenets of liberal democracy.31 They are not only impossible to harmonize with the political model of liberal democracy but also with European values as expressed in the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (1950). Even within a broad margin of appreciation of national regimes to place their own emphasis in interpreting the relationship between state and religion, theocracy and political atheism can never be reconciled with the ideas on which the European Convention was built.32 So the real discussion focuses on the three intermediate models. Which one is the most appropriate? And in particular: which one is most likely to accommodate radical movements and foster a sense of national social cohesion?

2. The resurrection of theocracy

It is important to understand that we evaluate the models against a specific social and political background of increasing radicalism in religion. Recently, much attention has been paid to the influence that “neoconservatives” exerted on American foreign policy.33 Much less attention has been given to the “theoconservatives” as a major factor in American politics.34 One of the most influential “theocons” is Richard John Neuhaus (1936-),35 who was an important influence on the Bush administration, in particular with regard to its attempts to tear down the “Wall of Separation.” The Bush administration maintained warm relations with Christian Evangelical circles.36

Neuhaus writes that politics and religion are different enterprises. But what he opposes is what he calls “the naked public square.”37 He continues:

The naked public square is the result of political doctrine and practice that would exclude religion and religiously grounded values from the conduct of public business. The doctrine is that America is a secular society. It finds dogmatic expression in the ideology of secularism. I will argue that the doctrine is demonstrably false and the dogma exceedingly dangerous.38

This passage exhibits a tendentious rousing of public sentiment. The vocabulary that Neuhaus uses to attack the idea of secularism is too vague and therefore inapt for the intricate discussion we are conducting with regard to this topic.

First, Neuhaus makes no mention of the distinction between state and society. And this distinction is crucial. The primary aim of secularism is not to make “society” secular. What political secularism tries to achieve is a religiously neutral state. And “neutrality” is interpreted as the absence of religious preference. But that leaves society and the individual citizen with the freedom to cultivate religious beliefs and to manifest allegiances in the public sphere.

Refer to more articles:  Which Of The Following Is Correct About The Lemon Law

Second, Neuhaus seems wrong on empirical grounds when he contends that Western societies are societies with a “naked public square.” On the contrary, never before did we see such religiously pluriform societies as nowadays. What Neuhaus means, perhaps, is that there is no longer one specific religion that binds us all, but that is, of course, something entirely different. What contemporary societies manifest is religious diversity. And this diversity is possible because Western constitutional traditions operate on the basis of what I have called “political secularism.”

Therefore Neuhaus’s statement that “Christian truth” is “public truth”39—as if that were something special—is misleading. Not only is “Christian truth” “public truth,” but every other kind of “truth” is “public truth” as well, in the sense that people are accustomed to communicate “truth” to each other and this process is protected by civil liberties, freedom of speech being among those principles.

Third, Neuhaus insinuates that religion is “excluded” by doctrinaire convictions or perhaps even by judicial means, from society, but this is not the case. On the contrary, the first amendment protects the free exercise of religion. There are no people—as he claims—who want to “keep the public square naked of religious symbol,” because everyone can manifest his/her religious beliefs in society. So Neuhaus does not really say what he means. What he means, perhaps, is that he wants Christian symbols to be visible in the public sphere and probably financed by the government because the country he lives in is considered to be a Christian country.

Fourth, Neuhaus uses a rhetorical and, we could say, misleading concept of secularism, identifying it with a kind of forced secularization of society. He writes:

The case can be made that the great social and political devastations of our century have been perpetrated by regimes of militant secularism, notably those of Hitler, Stalin and Mao.40

The conclusion that Neuhaus draws is that “the naked public square is a dangerous place.”41 He contends that when religious transcendence is excluded the space is opened to “demons aspiring to transcendent authority.”42

Neuhaus fails to see that these are all very different claims. That Nazism, Stalinism, and Maoism have caused great havoc in the twenty-first century cannot, of course, be contested. But what made those regimes so despicable was not that they did not profess belief in the Christian God. Atheism was also not the cause of the violation individual rights. Besides, not all of those regimes were so “atheistic” as Neuhaus claims them to be. Adolf Hitler was not an atheist.43 The cult around Stalin has religious tenets. When Joseph Stalin established his rule in the late 1920s, he introduced the obligation of the members of the Communist party to repent. Party members that had entertained what we might call “heretical” ideas and convictions were obliged to admit them publicly and acknowledge the correctness of Stalin’s general line.44

Neuhaus also mixes up political atheism (or “forced atheism”) of model 1 with the religiously neutral state of model 2. A supporter of laïcité who advocates that the state remain neutral in religious matters, does not advocate that the state should persecute citizens who, on the basis of their individual rights, profess the belief in some transcendent faith. Finally, Neuhaus seems to subscribe to a controversial theory that whoever does not believe in the Judeo-Christian God would be an easy prey for all kinds of superstition: “the space is opened to seven demons aspiring to transcendent authority.”45

3. The vitality of political Islam or Islamism

Even more apposite to illustrate the recent revival of religious political thinking is the upsurge of “political Islam” or “Islamism.” In the 1970s there was a widespread revival of political-religious movements in the Middle East, having wide reverberations in other parts of the world. Some key dates are: 1969, 1979, 1989.

In 1969 the Iranian religious and political leader Ayatollah Khomeini published a tract that is generally considered to be one of the most important documents of political Islam: Velayate Faqih.46 In this text Khomeini tells us that the Jews and other tribes that were even more satanic than the Jews tried to establish a completely wrong vision of Islam. In this false version of Islam they tried to deny the “revolutionary dimension” of Islam. They also contended that Islam was not a social religion, but something that was only concerned with the inner tranquility of the soul, claimed Khomeini.47

These are prima facie not very disturbing views. They may even be seen as legitimate criticism of the lack of freedom of religion in the West, in particular in the Soviet Union where religion, inluding the Islamic religion, was forcefully suppressed. But Khomeini’s argument becomes more disturbing when he tells us that the Prophet was “also a politician.” The prophet installed governors, operated as a judge, contracted treaties with foreign powers—in short: he was not only a religious but a political authority as well.

This idea that religious and worldly power should reside in the same hands is, of course, well known in the Western tradition, but, generally speaking, the experiences with this type of government have not been favorable. We can discern two variants. The first model is theocracy. Theocracy means, according to the French contemporary philosopher Tzvetan Todorov (1939-), that worldly power is simply put in the service of religious power.48 In other words: the religious leader is also the political leader. In Europe this implied: the Pope is superior to the emperor. The other variant is the opposite. Here the emperor is superior to the religious power. We call this caesaro-papism. In other words the emperor or the king is the overlord of the church. So it is the emperor who decides what is to be the religion of the land. He can appoint the religious leaders and control their behavior and he even adjudicates in doctrinal differences.

The struggle between pope and emperor raged on for many centuries in Europe.49 This struggle ended with the separation of worldly and religious power. Each is sovereign within its own domain. The political ideas revived by Khomeini would undo that separation.

Another problem with Khomeini’s confusion of religious and political power is that he implicitly violates the principles of the separation of powers as laid down by Montesquieu in his The Spirit of the Laws (1748). The legislative, administrative, and judicial branches should be separated in order to prevent abuse of power.50 The general idea behind the separation of powers is that divided power is limited power. And limited power is the general idea behind constitutionalism which, next to democracy, one is of the central tenets of good government.51

Khomeini’s approach therefore violates the central ideas of the European political order and the principles of the European Union, the European Convention of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, and the idea of liberal democracy that animates the political development in Europe since the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.

It is therefore a disquieting idea that Khomeini not only advocates his political model for Iran but for the rest of the world as well. He tells us that the “laws of Islam” are not dependent on time and place. They are valid for all eternity and have to be executed.52

It is clear that, under the garb of the seemingly innocuous thesis that Islam is a “social religion” and a “religion of life,” Khomeini in fact initiates a religious-political ideology that is inimical to the central tenets of good government which are enshrined in human rights treaties and in the constitutions of European states. His is, in fact, a totalitarian approach to politics.53

One can also put it differently: Khomeini tries to reinstall theocracy as a political model. It is the religious power that oversees the political power. Theocracy has to rule over democracy.

As stated above, in 1969 Khomeini’s highly influential tract on Islamic government was published.54 Ten years later, in 1979, his ideology gained actual political power in Iran, and ten after that, in 1989, the Berlin Wall broke down and the conflict between the East (Marxism) and the West (Liberalism) ended. But did this imply the demise of all ideological conflicts, as Fukuyama was hastily concluding?55 Or were there new challenges for what Fukuyama had dubbed “liberal democracy”?

Fukuyama should have noticed that in 1989, with the tenth anniversary of the Iranian regime, there was apparently a new ideology on the world historical stage that commanded the adherence of a considerable amount of people. This new ideology was “Islamism” or “political Islam.”56 The political leaders of this new ideology, Khomeini being the most prominent among them, revitalized the ideal of the ecclesiastic-statesman, the religious and political leader in one. Theocracy, a model deemed dead, rose from the ashes as the mythological phoenix.

The self-confidence of the new ideology challenging the dominance of liberal democracy appears clearly from the first major message to a foreign head of state that Khomeini had sent since the revolution. It was a personal letter to Mikhail Gorbachev (1931-). In this revealing letter Khomeini noted the failure of Marxism and admonished the Russian leader to look for spiritual renewal to the south:

I strongly urge that in breaking down the walls of Marxist fantasies you do not fall into the prison of the West and the Great Satan… . I call upon you seriously to study and conduct research into Islam… . I openly announce that the Islamic Republic of Iran, as the greatest and most powerful base of the Islamic world, can easily help fill up the ideological vacuum of your system.57

Eduard Shevardnadze (1928-), the Soviet Minister of Foreign Affairs, informed Khomeini that “all the members of the Soviet Presidium have studied the contents of Your Eminence’s message. No doubt we agree on a number of major points, but there are certain points on which we disagree.” Daniel Pipes comments: “One cannot get much meeker than ‘there are certain points on which we disagree.’”58

4. Why theocracy is important again

The new turn towards theocracy as an actual political system also implied a new relevance of the theocratic doctrine. Fukuyama did not mention theocratic movements as a new challenge to the ideology of liberal democracy in 1989. On the contrary, he rather dismissively wrote:

Our task is not to answer exhaustively the challenges to liberalism promoted by every crackpot messiah around the world, but only those that are embodied in important social or political forces and movements, and which are therefore part of world history.59

With the wisdom of hindsight this was perhaps his greatest miscalculation in a mostly visionary essay.60 There was at least one “crackpot messiah” that had ignited a revolution: Khomeini in Iran. And in 1989, when Fukuyama was writing his book, the Iranian Republic posed a considerable challenge to the Western world. Could Fukuyama retort that Islamism is not an ideology that is “embodied in important social or political forces and movements”? I think not. That would be overly optimistic, if not naïve. Gradually, Western scholars had to learn that “crackpot messiahs” had more influence than one might suppose. And that implicates that we have to read their scriptures in order to know what motivates them and their acolytes.61

It would be a bit haughty as well as not very fruitful politically to dismiss their ideas as “obsolete,” “medieval,” “crazy,” “cracked,” or simply not very serious. When mad medievalism successfully runs for office, we have some cause for concern. And radical groups in real states such as Saudi Arabia, Afghanistan, or Sudan see theocracy as a political goal to be realized. Even in countries like Turkey or Egypt theocracy has a less negative image today than it used to.62 We may put it this way: Albania or the Soviet Union are no role-models for the contemporary world, but Iran, in a certain sense, is. It is for that very reason that the study of Stalin and Lenin has historical significance, while the works by Sayyid Qutb (1906-66), Ayatollah Khomeini (1902-89), Hassan al-Banna (1906-49), Ibn Taymiyya (1263-1328), and other ideologues of radical Islam are relevant to our contemporary predicament that is not yet acknowledged by the general public.63

The London bombings; the murder of the Dutch filmmaker Theo van Gogh (1957-2004) by a home-grown jihadist on November 2, 2004; the Danish cartoon crisis that raged all over Europe in February 2006—these are all manifestations, so it seems, of a new assertion of self-confidence of radical Islamist groups. It seems correct to repeat after the chairman of the French commission, which defended the old constitutional ideal of laïcité, that secularist ideals are challenged nowadays by religious extremists.64

In a ruling by a Dutch court of January 23, 2008,65 four years after the murder,66 the murderer of Van Gogh gave some new insight into his motives. He declared:

The reason for the murder of Van Gogh is that he offended the Prophet. According to the law, he deserved the death penalty which I have executed… . Theo van Gogh considered himself to be a soldier. He fought against Islam. On November 2, Allah sent a soldier to cut his throat… .This is Jihad in the most literal sense. Van Gogh saw himself as a soldier and he had to be slaughtered. Van Gogh knew what he was doing. He stepped into the arena.67

Van Gogh had made a film, together with the Dutch parliamentarian Ayaan Hirsi Ali, on the predicament of women in the Muslim world. Van Gogh’s open letter to Hirsi Ali, a notorious critic of Islam, which stated that she was meant to be a next target, was pinned on the murder victim’s chest. During the last trial in which Mohammed B. appeared, the murderer declared that Hirsi Ali stepped “into the arena” and marched in the “ranks of the soldiers of evil.” He added:

She has offended the Prophet, she is an apostate, and she has associated with the enemy. Three reasons each in itself sufficient to qualify for the death penalty… . From the moment that she went into politics and declared her oath in Parliament she became an apostate… . I left the “Open letter to Hirshi Ali” on the corpse of Theo van Gogh to make a clear statement… . That statement is: it is war and if you enter the arena you know what will happen.68

Especially the last point is interesting in relation to the five models we have delineated. From the moment Hirsi Ali was sworn in into her political office she was, according to B., an “apostate.” She affiliated herself with the enemy.

What can we make of this? Apparently, the home-grown terrorist B. is severely opposed to democracy as a political system.

Refer to more articles:  Which Tera Raids Drop Herba Mystica

B. claims that one cannot be both a true believer and a member of parliament in a democracy. He does not use the word “theocracy,” but this concept seems appropriate here. And according to the Jihadist, there is a sharp contrast between democracy and theocracy. A theocracy is a government by God (“theos”); democracy, on the other hand, is a government by the people (“demos”). It is impossible for God and the people to be on the same level. In other words: one cannot both serve God and “us the people.” There can only be one final source of sovereignty. Either God is the ultimate source of our laws or this sovereignty is vested in the people. We are either ruled by sharia-law or by man-made law. According to the violent theocrat, there simply can be no compromise. Contemporary European societies have to deal with radical minorities who defy the authority of the national state. That poses a new challenge to the traditional paradigms of thinking about the relation between state and religion.

5. The model of the state church

The fourth way government can relate to religion is by establishing a state church. Among the twenty-five countries within the European Union seven have a state church. This is the case with Denmark, Finland, Norway, Sweden, Greece, Great Britain, and Malta.69 Measured against the backdrop of a religiously pluralist society, the idea of a state church is problematic. The fourth model is a relic from the past when European societies were much more homogenous, and one specific religion could function as the common bond of society. In that sense it is a “pre-modern” model. It has a great historical significance, as can be illustrated with reference to the Netherlands or Great Britain.

The Dutch Union of Utrecht (1579) inaugurated a certain amount of religious freedom. One had learned from the past that religion could be the source of endless strife. This could tear society apart and if we would wish to avoid that, the best way to do this would be to realize religious freedom. So in the Union of Utrecht religious freedom was acknowledged to a certain extent. “A certain extent,” because the Reformed Church still had a privileged position.70

The idea of the state church is easily combined with the idea of the nation-state. It is based on cuius regio, eius religio. The region determines the religion; more precisely: the king decides what is to be the religion of the land. Because that religion is the same for all citizens, religion can function as the bond of social cohesion.

In a multidenominational or pluralist society—as most European societies are nowadays—this model seems nostalgic or romantic. It is something adored by Romantics such as the German poet Novalis (1772-1801) in his book Die Christenheid oder Europa (1799). Novalis’s ideas are steeped in the longing for the one and only unifying religion: Christianity.71 But the chances that one religion—whether it be Christianity, Islam, the Jewish religion, or any other creed—will gain the upper hand on European soil in the foreseeable future is not very likely.

Nevertheless, Romanticism did not die with Novalis. There are a host of contemporary intellectuals that refer to “our Judeo-Christian civilization” that should be protected against the inroads of the alien Islam or the spirit of modern culture, usually characterized as “Enlightenment.”72 If those advocates of Judeo-Christian culture want to show that Christianity and the Jewish religion had a great influence on European civilization no one could reasonably disagree. But the question is not where we come from but in what direction we are developing.73 It is in this respect that the popular Muslim teacher and academic Tariq Ramadan is more realistic than his many critics who sometimes seem to dream about a uniquely European civilization with its “roots” in Judeo-Christian culture. The cultural historian can muse over the roots of European civilization; the political philosopher must reflect on the future course of events. And the society of the future will probably be pluralist and multicultural.

6. The religiously neutral state v. the multicultural state

Let me recapture what my conclusions are, so far. For the first model, political atheism, there are no adherents left.74 The fourth model, state church, is mainly defended by stealthily indicating what Europe and the West owes to Christianity. In most cases such comments are restricted to a historical reflection on the sources of inspiration of European civilization. And as far as historical commentary is concerned, there is nothing wrong with that, of course. The problem arises when those revealing the Christian roots of European civilization shift to defending Christianity as the basis for our contemporary legal institutions and shared morality. Those who take that step are defenders of the model of the state church. But this fourth model is not suitable for a multicultural and pluralist society.

The fifth model, theocracy, has followers in Western states, especially among radicalized youth, but the majority of people (including Muslims) agree that we should try to stay clear of it. Because political atheism (the first model) is obsolete, the discussion focuses on the following, intimately linked questions. First, what model is the most appropriate to avoid theocracy? Second, what model is fair with regard to people with diverse religious backgrounds, i.e. able to safeguard their freedom of religion and yet prevent the free exercise of religion from sapping the principles of a democratic legal order. In other words: what model is the most appropriate to prevent theocracy (the fifth model) from gaining ground and at the same time suitable to regulate pluralist society? This implies: the debate will focus in the coming years on the second and the third models: on the religiously neutral state (the second model) and multiculturalism (the third model).75

Within the Europe there are two countries that play a prominent role: on the one hand France—the most outspoken representative of the second model; on the other hand Great Britain—the prototype of a multiculturalist state.

What are the most important arguments advanced against multiculturalism (model 3)? And vice versa: what critique is raised at the model of the religiously neutral state (model 2)?

7. Arguments against multiculturalism

The first thing we have to realize is that multiculturalism is a kind of pluralism.76 And pluralism can be underestimated but it can be overstated as well. Under the present circumstances we are more prone to overestimate the amount of pluralism than underestimate it. Here is a characteristic statement from Noel Annan (1916-2000), a prominent British intellectual giving a portrait of “his age,” i.e. post-war Britain: “The brave new world was to be a pluralist world. People should acknowledge that there was no single model of belief and behaviour, such as that of the gentleman in bygone days.”77 But what Annan does not fully realize is that the glorification of pluralism underestimates the fact that our daily intercourse is based on countless implicit rules that we honor in our practice without consciously talking about them. We do not fight over our differences, for instance. We do not behead someone who tramples on our most sacred beliefs. We presuppose that people speak the truth unless we have reason to think otherwise. We consider it important that someone does not contradict himself in discussions over value preferences. We consider every rational disputant worthy of an answer if his arguments seem cogent. This points in the direction of a wider consensus on values that most people are inclined to acknowledge. What this all means, is that pluralism can easily be overstated as is the case in this remark by Annan. His portrait of his generation is full of those implicit understandings, although the writer does not notice them because they are experienced as more or less self-evident.

A more normative complaint that secularists voice about multiculturalism is that, although it presents itself as bringing social cohesion in society, it in fact undermines that cohesion.78 One may also put it in another way: Multiculturalism reinforces the ties between the different religious and ethnic communities but weakens the national bond. This has to do with the role that religion plays in the multiculturalist approach. Religion fosters the ties of the religious community and weakens the idea of national social cohesion. A religious terrorist obeying the laws of his religious community even if those violate national laws is an extreme but not altogether alien manifestation of that process.

Arguably, the religiously neutral state is in a better position than the multiculturalist state to foster social cohesion. The religiously neutral state says that it does not recognize nor finance nor support any religious direction (“La République ne reconnaît, ne salarie ni ne subventionne aucun culte,” according to the law of 1905 that introduced laïcité as an important principle of the French constitutional order).79 The American Republic proclaims the same in the First Amendment to the Constitution: “Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion… .”80 By not reinforcing the influence of religion on society the religiously neutral state might be better equipped to foster a sense of national cohesion. The religiously neutral state sees the bond of society in religiously neutral values of good citizenship.

8. Does the religiously neutral state violate individual rights?

Nevertheless, the religiously neutral state is heavily criticized by those who advocate more rights for religious beliefs. One of the most frequently voiced objections to neutralism is that this violates the civil rights of believers. It is an old complaint. In 1872, the laïcist politician and French premier Léon Gambetta (1838-82) wrote that the enemies of laïcité indict the secularists for not honoring the principle of freedom of conscience, and claim that laïcists persecute people for their convictions (“Nos adversaires disent que nous sommes les ennemis de la liberté de conscience, que nous persécutons les consciences”).81 But defenders of the secular state vehemently deny this. The laïcist position, in the words of the French socialist leader Jean Jaurès (1859-1914), one of the foremost ideologists of the secular state, “respects and completely assures the necessary freedom of all consciences, all creeds, all cults, but it does not accept any dogma as the basis of social life” (“Elle respecte, elle assure l’entière liberté de toutes les consciences, de toutes les croyances, de tous les cultes, mais elle ne fait d’aucun dogme la règle et le fondement de la vie sociale”).82

The question is topical again with regard to the discussion on the veil or headscarf in French schools.83 The discussion started in 1989 when two girls wearing headscarves were expelled from a school in Creil (Oise).84 The minister of Education, Lionel Jospin (1937-), tried to find a compromise, but the matter soon developed into a national debate. Some public intellectuals, including Régis Debray (1940-), Élisabeth Badinter (1944-), and Alain Finkelkraut (1949-) published an article in the French magazine Le Nouvel Observateur under the title “Teachers, do not capitulate.”85 Those writers warned against a kind of “Munich of the republican school.” They were answered by the sociologist Alain Touraine (1925-) and the politician Harlem Désir (1959-) who stressed that the expulsion of the girls wearing headscarves would be a real tragedy.86

Jospin asked the Conseil d’État for a judgment. The Conseil d’État came up with something of a compromise. It proclaimed that the wearing of religious symbols is not in itself incompatible with laïcité, provided that this is not done in an “ostentatious” manner.

However, this was considered to be too vague to be helpful for the educational institutions, and on the July 3, 2003 the French president Jacques Chirac (1932-), established a commission to inquire into the present-day meaning of laïcité.87 This was the commission Stasi, named after Bernard Stasi, whose report has been cited above. Stasi presented the findings of the commission on December 11, 2003. Meanwhile, the legislative process was working at full speed. On March 15, 2004, the parliament passed a law revitalizing the ideas of laïcité, that is to say: reinforced the principles outlined in the law of 1905 which for the first time legally established the separation of church and state.

This implied that from March 15, 2004 onwards Muslim girls were not allowed to wear ostentatious religious symbols in French schools. The veil and the headscarf, being such ostentatious symbols, were banned.

According to some commentators, this violates the freedom of religion of the girls who want to wear their religious symbols.88 Is this a convincing argument against neutralism?

I will try to gauge the significance of the religiously neutral state as a model that might be operative for other liberal democracies coping with a multicultural citizenry as well. The French system appears prima facie well equipped to integrate a considerable amount of people with non-Western backgrounds. But if this success is only accomplished on the basis of a discriminatory politics, that is a heavy price to pay, indeed. Let us inquire further into the criticism that is being directed at laïcité.

9. Why working in the civil service implies religious neutrality

Before we can judge whether the ban on religious symbols violates civil liberties (and does it to an extent that is unacceptable) we have to place this in perspective. Usually, one talks about a ban on religious symbols in the “public sphere.” That is hopelessly vague, as we have seen discussing the work of John Neuhaus.89 What is the “public sphere”? A firm distinction should be made between the state and society. Both belong to the “public sphere,” but the regime of laïcité concerns the state. So the first situation we have to distinguish is that of someone working in the civil service, in particular in professions where a high ethos of objectivity is expected. That is the case with policemen, people serving in the army, but also judges and public prosecutors. They all wear special attire to indicate that their work requires a certain objectivity and neutrality. Now, what is the situation when one of those civil servants objects to wearing religiously neutral clothing because he or she wants to wear a crucifix, a veil, or a yarmulke? The answer must be that in this situation, invoking civil rights would be somewhat misleading or at least very different from the situation of an ordinary citizen claiming his civil rights.

It is therefore not surprising that the European Court of Human Rights in Strasbourg has recognized the right of the state to make law that safeguards the neutrality of the state in education. In Dahlab v. Switzerland (February 15, 2001) a judgment was presented on a case about a teacher in the canton of Geneva. The teacher was not willing to abandon her headscarf although she had been subjected to several disciplinary measures by the school authorities. Those measures did not violate the European Convention, according to the European judges in Strasbourg.90 In Valsamis v. Greece (July 6, 1995), measures taken against a pupil violating the school rules could not be justified by an appeal to religious freedom.91

Refer to more articles:  Which Of The Following Is Tax-deductible To The Firm

The question of the religious symbols is intimately related to a more general question, i.e. whether civil servants should have the right to express their opinions, even if those opinions contradict the general policy of their political superiors. Not only in France but also in other liberal democracies this is a highly contested issue. If the civil servant could express his own views instead of those of his political superiors (ultimately those of the state itself), it would be tantamount to undermining the presuppositions on which liberal democracy rests, as so many political theoreticians have emphasized. One such theoretician is the British political scientist Herman Finer.

Herman Finer (1898-1969), the brother of the political scientist and historian Samuel Finer (1915-1993), was the son of Romanian Jewish parents, who joined the staff of the London School of Economics in 1920, resigning in 1942 to become professor of political science at the University of Chicago from 1945 to 1968.92 He was a passionate democrat, an anti-Marxist and anti-fascist.93 His major work is The Theory and Practice of Modern Government (1932, revised in 1949), based upon the study of four democracies: Britain, the US, France, and Weimar Germany.94 What is important within the context of the secular outlook is Finer’s analysis of the loyalty of the civil service in a democratic state. He proposed his ideas in British civil service (1937)95 and in other writings. The relevant question is: “Are the servants of the public to decide their own course, or is their course of action to be decided by a body outside themselves?”96 Finer’s answer is that the servants of the public are not to decide their own course; they are to be responsible to the elected representatives of the public, and those are to determine the course of action of the public servants “to the most minute degree that is technically possible.”97 This would leave no room for individual self-expression of the members of the civil service, to be sure. But does that not violate the civil rights of civil servants? And, if so, why should we be so harsh on them?

The treatment of the civil servants has to do with the internal logic of a system of representative government. Finer contends that the only form of self-government worthy of the name is government through ministers responsible to an elective legislature. But that system rests on certain presuppositions that are not always made explicit. One of those presuppositions will be made clear by means of an anecdote about Sir Oswald Ernald Mosley (1896-1980), founder of the British Union of Fascists. During a political manifestation a skeptical citizen asked him: “How can I get rid of you, if you don’t please me?”98 That was not something that had occurred to Mosley. He had pondered upon how to get elected, not how to leave the stage in case of political failure in the eyes of the people he claimed to represent.

In the second half of nineteenth century European states developed a mechanism for the non-violent removal of ruling elites in case they would no longer “please” the citizen. Democracy is a system “in which the people can at regular intervals constitutionally dismiss the governors if they so choose.”99 The device to accomplish a bloodshed-free circulation of political elites is called “ministerial responsibility.” Ministerial responsibility is the constitutional convention in governments using the Westminster System that a cabinet minister bears the ultimate responsibility for the actions of their ministry or department.100 Since the development of ministerial responsibility in the second half of the twentieth century, democracy is predicated on the notion of ministerial accountability. This means that the minister has to justify the policies of the state towards Parliament and not towards the King.101 If Parliament is dissatisfied (and remains dissatisfied) with the course of action proposed or actually effected by the government, the responsible politicians have to be replaced by other politicians. This is the way democracy functions. Thus the system places a heavy responsibility on politicians. Their power is circumscribed by the power of the representative body that can remove them from office. Now (and here individual self-expression of civil servants comes in), this responsibility can only be effective if the minister has great powers over the civil service as well. He must be sure that the civil service executes his orders. “What is needed,” says Finer, “is not technical capacity per se, but technical capacity in the service of the public welfare as defined by the public and its authorized representatives.”102 To make this system work the technical expert has to be subservient to the political powers. And here the idea of a religiously neutral state comes in. In its ultimate consequences this idea implies the complete renunciation by those working in the civil service of all ambition to exert political power or to manifest a personal worldview.

Another great scholar whose name is intimately linked with this idea is the German sociologist Max Weber (1864-1920). Weber’s famous definition of state has been introduced above. In Weber’s vision of politics, power plays an overriding role. His commentaries on this topic could even be read as cynical by a more idealistic audience. Nevertheless, his characterization of the state as hierarchical organization would nonetheless form the basis for the development of democratic doctrine because only when power is concentrated in a certain point it can be limited and subjected to certain controls. Weber sees the public administration as a hierarchically organized civil service and in his Politik als Beruf (1919) or The Profession and Vocation of Politics103 he develops the idea of a strict submission of the civil service to political leadership—in general, reiterating Herman Finer’s ideas discussed above. Weber notoriously pointed out that without the loyalty of the civil service the whole machinery would stagnate (“ohne diese im höchsten Sinn sittliche Disziplin und Selbstverleugnung zerfiele der ganze Apparat”).104 If and only if the loyalty of the civil service is secured, the minister can bear responsibility for policy decisions towards Parliament.

The loyalty of the civil service would be undermined, however, if the civil service as whole or individual civil servants would partake in political discussions, advocate political ideologies, manifest their religious alliances, or in another way bertay their personal predilections in contradiction with the official policy of the state. The right to manifest your personal religious affiliations, although an important civil right or human right, cannot be fully accorded to those working in the civil service. At least that is the case in a democratic state. This fact was also recognized by the European Court of Human Rights in Strasbourg in the case Ahmed v. United Kingdom (1998).105

A British law prohibiting civil servants to engage in politics was not violating the principles of the European Convention, according to the European Court in Strasbourg. I would consider this to be an understatement. The loyalty of the civil service to their political superiors is not only not violating the principles of the European democratic political order but it is an essential ingredient of it. Democracy is impossible without this loyalty. The loyalty of the civil servants is as important for sane democracy as divine revelation is for theocracy.

It is clear that the situation of people working in the civil service is completely different from that of ordinary citizens. Freedom of religion, freedom of speech, the “right to read”—as it it called by Paul Blanshard106—imply that ordinary citizens can exercise their religious freedom in society. But democracy prohibits civil servants from appealing civil rights in order to manifest their religious and political orientation if it is at odds with the ideas of the cabinet. The principles of the secular state or religiously neutral state are in harmony with democratic theory.

The upshot of all this is that those working for the state cannot be allowed to display religious symbols. Thus policemen, civil servants, servicemen, and members of the judiciary should be “religiously neutral.”

10. The position of ordinary citizens

Now let us set aside the status of the civil servant and focus on the ordinary citizen. Should the ordinary citizen (as distinguished from the civil servant) also refrain from wearing religious symbols? What about the girls in French schools, for instance? Those girls, not being teachers, certainly do not represent the authority of the state. So the argument that is applicable to the civil servants does not apply to them. Should not this imply that the prohibition of the headscarf is illegitimate as far as ordinary citizens are concerned? Should not human rights have priority over other considerations in this context?

The French do not think so but, as appears from the foregoing considerations, a ban on the headscarf worn by students has to be based on different grounds than neutrality of the civil service. The neutrality of the civil service would only justify a ban on the headscarf for teachers. How to justify the fact that the students are not allowed to wear religious symbols?

The core of the French argument against students displaying religious symbols is that they are the weaker party in relation to their fathers, brothers, priests, imams, and other people placed in a formal or informal hierarchical relation to them. We may put this as follows: laïcité à la française chooses to protect the integrity of the child against the real or supposed religious rights and interests of the parents. The French want the school to be a refuge against social tensions. At school, the child should be allowed to make his or her own choices, even if those contradict the choices of their parents.107 But, of course, this is not an exclusively French idea. The British philosopher Grayling said: “Let us challenge religion to leave children alone until they are adults, whereupon they can be presented with the essentials of religion for mature consideration.”108

From the point of view of laïcité the school is the main protector of the freedom of conscience for young people. Children should not be indoctrinated but be allowed to develop their own ideas. They should be educated to become moral and autonomous agents. This is why laïcist philosophers and politicians emphasize the importance reading has for children. In an address to school instructors in 1888, Jean Jaurès proclaimed that everything starts with reading. It is absolutely necessary that children learn how to read (“Il faut d’abord que vous appreniez aux enfants à lire avec une facilité absolue, de telle sorte qu’ils ne puissent plus l’oublier de la vie et que, dans n’importe quel livre, leur oeil ne s’arrête à aucun obstacle. Savoir lire vraiment sans hésitation, comme nous lisons nous en moi, c’est la clé de tout”).109

Children’s education is also important for the preservation of democracy itself. Children have to learn about the principles of democratic government and the attitude that they involve. It was again Jean Jaurès who proclaimed in 1904 that laïcité respects all religious convictions. It attributes no privileged status to any of them (“Elle respecte, elle assure l’entière liberté de toutes les consciences, de toutes les croyances, de tous les cultes, mais elle ne fait d’aucun dogme la règle et le fondement de la vie sociale”).110 But it is absolutely essential for the continuation of democracy and the secular state that the principles on which it rests are bequeathed to next generations. That implies that democracy has the duty to educate the youth. And the youth has the right to be educated according to the same principles that will later in life guarantee their freedom. No other institution has the right to frustrate this process (“La démocratie a le devoir d’éduquer l’enfance; et l’enfance a le droit d’être éduquée selon les principes mêmes qui assureront plus tard la liberté de l’homme. Il n’appartient à personne, ou particulier, ou famille ou congrégation, de s’interposer entre ce devoir de la nation et ce droit de l’enfant”).111

The French commission Stasi, which revived and reaffirmed the principles underlying the idea of the religiously neutral state,112 leaned heavily on the idea of the school as a refuge against social tensions. The commission’s reasoning behind the idea of the religiously neutral state was that wearing religious symbols was not a voluntary choice made by children but oftentimes was forced upon them.113 And where those more powerful apply pressure on those less powerful, the state has an obligation to protect the weaker party.

What this amounts to is that the religiously neutral state is possible in the sense that it does not violate the foundations of liberal democracy.114 The common arguments against it are only valid against the background of a multiculturalist ideology.

The religiously neutral state is not only possible, it may also be necessary against the background of religious radicalism and extremism that seems to grow among the youth of ethnic and religious minorities. Youngsters disaffected from European societies pose a security risk if they radicalize in Islamist ideologies that are being exported from countries like Iran, Saudi Arabia, and other strongholds of radical Islamist thought.115 European societies themselves cannot afford any longer to cultivate multiculturalist ideology that fosters religious communities and weakens the national state, as was the fashion in the 1970s and 1980s.

At present, there seems to be growing a vague sort of acknowledgment that European states have a problem with their radicalized youth,116 but there is still widespread ignorance about what exactly makes radical thought “radical” or “extreme.” That is, on the one hand, of course, that those people who are being radicalized are prepared to use violence to realize their aims.117 Yet there is something else that defines the religious terrorist: he (or she)118 lives in a mental world where national sovereignty has no place. Like Ayatollah Khomeini who condemned the British writer Salman Rushdie for crimes he did not perpetrate within the Iranian jurisdiction,119 the home grown terrorists simply do not feel bound to the national laws of the country where they live. Mohammed B., the home grown jihadist who killed the Dutch filmmaker Van Gogh, derived his inspiration and the legitimacy of his actions from a kind of universal religious law deemed to be higher than state law.120

Both the model of state church (and a concomitant plea for the revitalization of the Judeo-Christian roots of European culture) and the reaffirmation of the religiously neutral state can be understood as attempts to provide a basis for common citizenship. The problem with the reaffirmation of the Judeo-Christian roots, however, is that it is exclusionary towards ethnic and religious minorities. This is not the case with the attempt to find a religiously neutral basis for common citizenship. It is therefore the model of the religiously neutral state that has the best chances of providing a moral basis for the development of national social cohesion. Oscar Wilde once quipped: “It’s hard to prophesize, especially about the future.” And, of course, nobody can forecast what model of state-religion relations will prove to be most successful in “creating citizens.” What we can do, however, is to point out what model of available possibilities is the most likely to fulfill that role.

Related Posts

Which Plants Produce The Most Oxygen

What are the Highest Oxygen-Producing Plants? The highest oxygen-producing plants include Boston ferns, weeping figs, aloe vera, spider plants, gerbera daisies, areca palms, peace lilies, golden pathos,…

Which Is True About Scientific Inquiry

One thing is common to all forms of science: an ultimate goal “to know.” Curiosity and inquiry are the driving forces for the development of science. Scientists…

Which Zodiac Sign Is The Oldest

Which Zodiac Sign Is The Oldest

The Ancient Greeks — along with other civilizations of the time — widely believed in a now-iconic phrase: “As Above, So Below.” In other words, the Greeks…

Which Of The Following Is A Characteristic Of Beta

What Is Beta? Beta is a measure of a stock’s volatility in relation to the overall market. By definition, the market, such as the S&P 500 Index,…

Which Is Better Graphite Or Fiberglass Pickleball Paddle

Fiberglass vs Graphite Pickleball Paddle The pickleball arena resonates with the constant buzz of energetic gameplay and the clink of paddles. Among the myriad of considerations for…

Which Of The Following Best Describes The Paintbox Era

The Hay Wain, Study Artist: John ConstableYou may be interested Which Home Care Agency Pays The Most Which Phrase Best Describes Jazz Fusion Which Cave Is Located…